In recursion theory, α recursion theory is a generalisation of recursion theory to subsets of admissible ordinals . An admissible set is closed under functions, where denotes a rank of Godel's constructible hierarchy. is an admissible ordinal if is a model of Kripke–Platek set theory. In what follows is considered to be fixed.
The objects of study in recursion are subsets of . These sets are said to have some properties:
- A set is said to be -recursively-enumerable if it is definable over , possibly with parameters from in the definition.
- A is -recursive if both A and (its relative complement in ) are -recursively-enumerable. It's of note that -recursive sets are members of by definition of .
- Members of are called -finite and play a similar role to the finite numbers in classical recursion theory.
- Members of are called -arithmetic.
There are also some similar definitions for functions mapping to :
- A function mapping to is -recursively-enumerable, or -partial recursive, iff its graph is -definable in .
- A function mapping to is -recursive iff its graph is -definable in .
- Additionally, a function mapping to is -arithmetical iff there exists some such that the function's graph is -definable in .
Additional connections between recursion theory and α recursion theory can be drawn, although explicit definitions may not have yet been written to formalize them:
- The functions -definable in play a role similar to those of the primitive recursive functions.
We say R is a reduction procedure if it is recursively enumerable and every member of R is of the form where H, J, K are all α-finite.
A is said to be α-recursive in B if there exist reduction procedures such that:
If A is recursive in B this is written . By this definition A is recursive in (the empty set) if and only if A is recursive. However A being recursive in B is not equivalent to A being .
We say A is regular if or in other words if every initial portion of A is α-finite.